Teleology and Biology

In the ‘Moderation’ thread, William J Murray tried to make a case for ideological bias among evolutionary scientists by referencing a 2006 Gil Dodgen post, in which numerous authors emphasise the lack of teleology within the evolutionary process. I thought this might merit its own OP.

I disagree that authors are showing a metaphysical bias by arguing against teleology. I wrote

Evolutionary processes, conventionally defined (ie, variations and their changes in frequency due to differential survival and reproduction), do not have goals. If there IS an entity with goals that is also directing, that’s as may be, but the processes of evolution carry on regardless when it isn’t. It is important to erase the notion of teleology from a student’s mind in respect of evolutionary mechanisms of adaptation, and most of those quotes appear to have that aim. Organisms don’t, on the best evidence available, direct their own evolution.

To which WJM made the somewhat surprising rejoinder: “how do you know this”? Of course the simple answer is that I qualified my statement ‘on the best evidence available’ – I didn’t claim to know it. But there is a broader question. Is there any sense in which evolutionary processes could, even in principle, be teleological? I’d say not. You have a disparate collection of competing entities. Regardless whether there is a supervening entity doing some directing, the process of differential survival/reproduction/migration cannot itself have goals.

An example of evolution in action: the Chemostat.

The operator of a chemostat has a goal – often, to create a pure cell line. The process by which this is achieved is by simultaneous addition and removal of medium, which causes purification by random sampling, which is evolution (a form of genetic drift). How can that process have a goal? There is no collusion between the cells in the original medium to vote one to be the sole ancestor of all survivors. How do I know this? That would be a pretty daft question. I think it would be incumbent on the proponent to rule it in, rather than for me to rule it out.

690 thoughts on “Teleology and Biology

  1. Elizabeth:
    There might be definitions of “teleology” that don’t require an intender (and I suggest that those definitions are covered by “teleonomy”) but surely it’s intention we are interested in here?

    I think you have it backwards. There might be definitions of teleology that require an intender that are not covered by by “teleology,” but I can’t think of any.

  2. Gravity is caused by the mass of the Earth and has nothing to do with it’s spinning. The spinning of the Earth actually reduces the “gravity” felt by someone at the equator as compared to someone at one of the poles.

    LoL! Thanks Robin, that was worth the price of admission.

  3. William:

    Many behaviors have been shown to be sufficiently described in mechanistic terms; but many are also known not t be sufficiently described in mechanistic terms.

    The real question isn’t whether they’ve been “sufficiently described in mechanistic terms”, but rather whether they are thus describable in principle.

    Detailed mechanistic models can be impractical, as Lizzie points out, and we may choose to adopt a teleological stance to simplify things. It’s a convenience, not an in-principle necessity.

  4. Kantian Naturalist: As for physics: I’m inclined to follow Ladyman and Ross here in thinking that the only kind of physics which constrains all stance-relative ontological commitments is fundamental physics, which today consists of quantum mechanics, general relativity, and thermodynamics. Possibly dynamical systems theory could be considered a fundamental physical theory, but I simply don’t know.The “fundamental” means that any measurement taken anywhere in space or in time can confirm or disconfirm a hypothesis entailed by the theory.

    But, that’s actually a very loose constraint, and beyond that, “rainforest realism” reigns: there are many different real phenomena, and different stances track and classify real phenomena in different ways, and so we have a plurality of characterizations of reality.

    Addendum: some time ago I noted my support of Jay Rosenberg’s argument for “convergent realism” (the paper is here, but it’s on JSTOR and so probably inaccessible to most of you).

    I still find convergent realism quite appealing. But on the approach I’m now considering, convergent realism is even more limited than Rosenberg admitted. He thought that CR only held for quantitative natural science, because only when you have exact quantities that you can generate model theory change in terms of the Cauchy convergence.

    By contrast, if Ladyman and Ross are on the right track, convergent realism is true only of fundamental physics. There could perhaps be different convergences in the different sciences, but I’m more inclined to think that theories in the sciences are too domain-specific and context-dependent to generate the really strong inter-theoretic comparisons that convergent realism requires.

  5. keiths: Detailed mechanistic models can be impractical, as Lizzie points out, and we may choose to adopt a teleological stance to simplify things. It’s a convenience, not an in-principle necessity.

    I’m not so sure about that. A teleological stance can disclose real features of a system that exhibits organizational closure and thermodynamic openness (cf. Mossimo and Bich, cited above), where the systems have the right kind of dependence-and-independence from their environments.

    The only requirement that physics imposes is that our description of the difference between the linear causality of “mechanistic” systems and the circular causality of “teleological” systems does not involve backwards causation (violation of the arrow of time) or violation of the principle of causal closure of the universe.

    As far as I can tell, there’s nothing in fundamental physics (QM + GR + thermodynamics) which requires that the teleological stance is a mere convenience, a second-rate bookkeeping device, more of a heuristic than the mechanistic stance, less “real,” etc.

  6. keiths:
    William:

    The real question isn’t whether they’ve been “sufficiently described in mechanistic terms”, but rather whether they are thus describable in principle.

    Detailed mechanistic models can be impractical, as Lizzie points out, and we may choose to adopt a teleological stance to simplify things.It’s a convenience, not an in-principle necessity.

    Actually, I think it’s an in-principle necessity. For one reason, complex systems are chaotic – you can’t predict outcomes by simply knowing the starting values, as it were, even if the system is deterministic – you’ve still got to run the whole model to find the answer, which means the model is as large as the system you are trying to model. And with a non-deterministic system, you will have very little chance of getting anything like the same outcome twice. So chaotic systems are intrinsically unpredictable.

    But they nonetheless have higher-level properties – we can say things like: usually when we see A emerging, B follows. Or, when A intends B, B usually occurs.

    The classic example is weather patterns – we can’t make detailed forecasts of weather more than a few days ahead. But we can make general principles, that allow us to say, for instance, that this summer will be probably be a cool one, because of the el Nino, or that the temperature in November will probably be cooler than the temperature today.

    But those are system-level models, not models based on the parts, and they are have much larger error-bars on their predictions. That’s why statistics is so important in psychology! We can make general predictions about behaviour, but we are often wrong. We just hope that our generalisations are “statistically significant”.

  7. If the gravitational mass is equal to the inertial mass does it mean that they are the same thing? Do we know why the two values are equal, or is that still a mystery?

  8. Mung:

    If the gravitational mass is equal to the inertial mass does it mean that they are the same thing? Do we know why the two values are equal, or is that still a mystery?

    Einstein addressed that in his famous statement of the equivalence principle:

    A little reflection will show that the law of the equality of the inertial and gravitational mass is equivalent to the assertion that the acceleration imparted to a body by a gravitational field is independent of the nature of the body. For Newton’s equation of motion in a gravitational field, written out in full, it is:

    (Inertial mass) x (Acceleration) = (Intensity of the gravitational field) x (Gravitational mass)

    It is only when there is numerical equality between the inertial and gravitational mass that the acceleration is independent of the nature of the body.

  9. keiths:

    Detailed mechanistic models can be impractical, as Lizzie points out, and we may choose to adopt a teleological stance to simplify things. It’s a convenience, not an in-principle necessity.

    KN:

    I’m not so sure about that. A teleological stance can disclose real features of a system that exhibits organizational closure and thermodynamic openness (cf. Mossimo and Bich, cited above), where the systems have the right kind of dependence-and-independence from their environments.

    I’m skeptical, but let me read Mossimo and Bich before I respond.

  10. Neil Rickert: I don’t actually see any basis for that.

    Physics constrains physicists, and other people (particularly engineers) find it useful to follow some of those constraints.But I don’t see that it otherwise constrains anything.

    I should have said it constrains scientist theories in the special sciences. My bad.

  11. Kantian Naturalist: Possibly dynamical systems theory could be considered a fundamental physical theory, but I simply don’t know.

    A quick question while I think about a more substantive reply to the bulk of your posts.

    What do you mean by a DST?

    To me DST is just mathematics: viz, a coupled set of differential equations, usually including derivatives wrt to time (hence dynamic), along with the techniques for analyzing the trajectory of the variables through phase space.

    But when you say DST may be a fundamental physical theory, that makes me think you mean something else by DST.

  12. Elizabeth:
    It seems to me that if we want to talk about intention we need to talk about an intender. And an intender, I suggest, has to be some kind of sapient entity capable of both imagining alternative futures and of executing actions that will preferentially tend to bring one, rather than the other, about.

    Edward Feser writes:

    Similarly the “directedness” in terms of which modern philosophers characterize intentionality does not for the Aristotelian mark a difference between the material and the immaterial … intentionality, at least as typically understood by contemporary philosophers – again, as a matter of something’s being “directed” onto an object, or “pointing” beyond itself – is just a special case of this more general phenomenon of teleology or finality in nature. Indeed, the contemporary analytic philosopher George Molnar characterizes the causal powers even of inorganic phenomena as possessing “physical intentionality” insofar as these powers point to their typical effects, while another analytic philosopher, John Heil, speaks of the “natural intentionality” by virtue of which dispositional properties … point to their manifestations … And the biologist J. Scott Turner characterizes unconscious organic developmental processes as manifesting “intentionality” insofar as they point beyond themselves to a certain end state. All of these phenomena are, for the Aristotelian no less than for the materialist, entirely material.

    – Neo-Scholastic Essays. p. 222

    So no.

  13. Kantian Naturalist: I can accept quite easily that stances can overlap or bleed into each other, and in many cases we can and do adopt different stances towards the same object at the same time. For example, a physician treating her patient adopts both a discursive stance — treating the patient as a person with beliefs, desires, anxieties, etc. — and also a teleological stance — treating the patient as a diseased organism.

    I’m not sure what you mean by “bleed into”. So let me try my point again.

    Many scientific models based on mechanisms simultaneously incorporate two sciences. For example, neuroeconomics tries to link people’s decision processes with neuroscience. The phenomena and context come from economics; the components and their inter causal relations come from neuroscience.

    In your doctor scenario, an analogy would be explaining and treating a patient’s depression by drugs whose development was based on neurochemistry.

    It is not that someone takes two stances at the same time to look at different aspects of a situation, it is rather that two stances/sciences are integrated in a single mechanism crossing both.

    Again, I have no issues with rainforest realism. I just want to say science does build integrated models which mix ontologies from different sciences. So one’s approach to ontology and stances has to recognize that.

    BTW, I make no claims about the success of neuroeconomic models or whether we really understand the neuroscience of depression. Only that scientists are trying. to build models of that form.

    ON a related note, here is a skeptical article about neuroscience and politics. I thought it might interest you as it calls on the enactivists for support of its critique

  14. Can you summarise why you find this essay convincing? It concedes that neurons are switches. Why do you think that a “computational theory” of cognition “ignores the actual dynamics of living organisms”? What essential feature is, in your view, ignored?

  15. BruceS: I just want to say science does build integrated models which mix ontologies from different sciences. So one’s approach to ontology and stances has to recognize that.

    I appreciate your emphasis on that point. And thank you for the article on neuroscience and politics!

  16. Kantian Naturalist: (Incidentally, this is why I am no longer consider myself an “emergentist”, since “emergentism” does presume some “base” that has ontological primacy over whatever “emerges” from it.)

    I am not sure that emergetism requires that the base has ontological primacy.

    In fact, despite Ladyman and Ross, there still seems to be a lot of philosophical ink continuing to be spilled on defending the ontologically independent causal powers of the entities of the special sciences from Kim’s overdetermination arguments.

    For example, the Mossio and Bich paper you linked above cites an earlier paper of theirs which appears to be doing exactly that for their model of biological closure of constraints (I’ve only read the overview).

  17. BruceS: I am not sure that emergetism requires that the base has ontological primacy.

    Perhaps not, but it does strike me that emergentism is going to require something like the emerging and the emerged-from has ontological priority over the emerging/emergent. But even relative ontological priority is a slippery slope — which is different from the mere sanity that simpler systems appeared earlier in the being-becoming of the cosmos than more complex system. Cosmological priority is not (necessarily) ontological priority.

    In fact, despite Ladyman and Ross, there still seems to be a lot of philosophical ink continuing to be spilled on defending the ontologically independent causal powers of the entities of the special sciences from Kim’s overdetermination arguments.

    That’s a nice observation! But if Ladyman and Ross are basically right, then this ink spillage is unnecessary — rather, under the rules of ‘rainforest realism’, all of the special sciences characterize the entities of their respective domains as having independently specifiable causal powers! This gives us a very different way around Kim’s objections.

    I should note that, in what I’ve said here so far, I’ve been writing as if Ladyman and Ross’s scientific metaphysics (“the world is real patterns”) is roughly consistent with the process ontology that Evan Thompson inherits from Deleuze and Merleau-Ponty. I actually have no idea if those two approaches cohere or not, and I’m still waiting to find someone who can tell me if I’m talking sense or not.

  18. From a recent paper by Mark Okrent, author of Rational Animals. (The full paper is a criticism of Brandom’s interpretation of Heidegger; I assume this will not of much interest to most of you.)

    ——————————————————
    As I see it, here are all of the five autonomous layers of intentionality. (To say that the layers are autonomous is to say that it is possible for an agent to exhibit any of the lower layers without exhibiting the higher, but that it is not possible for an agent to exhibit any level of intentionality without also exhibiting all of the levels below it.) At the lowest level is the type of goal-directed teleology that is displayed by virtually all of the animals. The actions of such agents have goals, even though the agents themselves have no states that are about or directed towards anything. At the next highest level are those agents whose behavior exhibits instrumental rationality. Such agents, including many mammals and birds, not only do things in order to accomplish ends, they also do things for reasons of their own. There is no reason that such instrumentally rational agents can’t use found tools, and many of them do, even if such agents neither intend tools as to be used in socially prescribed ways nor act to improve the tools that they use. . . . At the next level are those animals, if there are such, that display both instrumental rationality and the rudimentary form of culture that is necessary to institute tool types as to be used in various socially prescribed ways, but do not display the kinds of interpretive activity, such as improvement and repair, that Heidegger marks as the necessary condition on discourse. Even such agents, however, are significantly different from us. As Bert Dreyfus puts the point in the title of the paper he has just given, ‘skillfully coping human beings differ from animals’. I would add, however, that such animals are essentially different from human beings, because human beings are self-interpreters. One level up from the social tool users are those non-linguistic tool users, if such exist, who not only use socially instituted tools, but interpret the roles that define those tools, and thereby themselves. . . The last layer at the top of the cake is language. It tastes good, and it is good for you, but unless all of the other layers are capable of autonomous existence, the linguistic top layer is impossible.

  19. At the lowest level is the type of goal-directed teleology that is displayed by virtually all of the animals. The actions of such agents have goals, even though the agents themselves have no states that are about or directed towards anything.

    To me this just sounds incoherent. =P

    Is there such a thing as non-goal-directed teleology?

    What does it mean to say that an agent has goals but no states that are about or directed towards those goals?

  20. Mung:
    What does it mean to say that an agent has goals but no states that are about or directed towards those goals?

    In context, by “state” Okrent means “mental state,” and specifically, mental states such as beliefs and desires. An animal can have goal-directed behavior without having any beliefs about the goal or desires to attain it. The main example Okrent uses in his book is the egg-laying behavior of the Sphenx wasp: fully teleological but not intentional.

  21. keiths, to William:

    The real question isn’t whether they’ve been “sufficiently described in mechanistic terms”, but rather whether they are thus describable in principle.

    Detailed mechanistic models can be impractical, as Lizzie points out, and we may choose to adopt a teleological stance to simplify things.It’s a convenience, not an in-principle necessity.

    Lizzie:

    Actually, I think it’s an in-principle necessity. For one reason, complex systems are chaotic – you can’t predict outcomes by simply knowing the starting values, as it were, even if the system is deterministic…

    You’re right that we can’t predict the longer-term behavior of deterministic, chaotic systems, but that is only because we don’t have the computational resources and can’t do infinite-precision math, in practice. A Laplacian demon wouldn’t share these limitations and could predict the long-term behavior of any deterministic system, chaotic or not.

    The limitations are in practice, not in principle.

    And with a non-deterministic system, you will have very little chance of getting anything like the same outcome twice.

    True, but that’s because of the non-determinism, not because of the chaos. A Laplacian demon with knowledge of the outcome of every nondeterministic event could in fact model a chaotic system perfectly.

  22. My overall point being that we include teleology in our models for practical reasons, not because it has a genuine existence apart from mechanism.

  23. Mung: I think you have it backwards. There might be definitions of teleology that require an intender that are not covered by by “teleology,” but I can’t think of any.

    I’ve read this several times, but I can’t parse it. Can you try again?

  24. keiths: You’re right that we can’t predict the longer-term behavior of deterministic, chaotic systems, but that is only because we don’t have the computational resources and can’t do infinite-precision math, in practice. A Laplacian demon wouldn’t share these limitations and could predict the long-term behavior of any deterministic system, chaotic or not.

    The limitations are in practice, not in principle.

    I think that is a distinction without a difference. Even the Laplacian demon with infinite computational resources and infinite precision maths would still have to run the entire simulation in order to find the answer.

  25. Reciprocating Bill,

    I’m surprised that Ruth Garrett Millikan hasn’t come up in the context of this discussion of function and purpose in biology. I’d expect Dennett to draw heavily upon her thesis in his upcoming book.

    I haven’t heard about Dennett’s upcoming book. What do you know about it?

  26. Lizzie,

    Even the Laplacian demon with infinite computational resources and infinite precision maths would still have to run the entire simulation in order to find the answer.

    Sure, but my point is that the demon’s simulation is nothing but a simulation of mechanism. It makes correct predictions without invoking teleology.

    Teleology is something we must invoke in practice, but it is not needed in principle. Mechanism is enough.

  27. But practice is all we’ve got, keiths.

    From within the system, the only way of modelling what happens in the system, when it concerns intentional agents, is at the intentional level. The point about the demon is that it is outside the system

    If it wants to model a fellow demon then it’s stuck.

    ETA: another way of putting this might be to say: a simulation can only be a good predictive model of a chaotic system if the simulation is not itself part of the model (and the system is deterministic, and all the starting values are known yadda yadda).

    In fact, of course, simulate is exactly what we do as intentional agent – we simulate the effects of alternative courses of action, and choose the course of action whose simulated outcome we prefer. And when predicting the actions of other intentional agents, we simply model this process at one remove: “If I was that person, I would do X”.

  28. evolution by definition must be teleological or it runs aground extremely fast.

    This is why the only way the darwinian evolution narrative survives is by co-opting 98% of what needs to be explained.

    Assume OoL. Assume reproduction, Assume multi-cellularity. Assume all the mechanisms required to handle the ramifications of reproduction and multi-cellularity.

    And viola, evolution works baby…….no shit, sherlock.

  29. Steve:
    evolution by definition must be teleological or it runs aground extremely fast.

    Can you explain what you mean by this?

    This is why the only way the darwinian evolution narrative survives is by co-opting 98% of what needs to be explained.

    Not really.

    Assume OoL.

    Certainly.

    Assume reproduction

    That’s implicit in OoL

    Assume multi-cellularity.

    Nope.

    Assume all the mechanisms required to handle the ramifications of reproduction and multi-cellularity.

    Nope.

    And viola, evolution works baby…….no shit, sherlock.

    I think you’ll find that Sherlock played the violin, not the viola.

  30. Kantian Naturalist: But if Ladyman and Ross are basically right, then this ink spillage is unnecessary — rather, under the rules of ‘rainforest realism’, all of the special sciences characterize the entities of their respective domains as having independently specifiable causal powers! This gives us a very different way around Kim’s objections.

    I suspect L-R does not help, but to explain why I need to review the usual approach to detemining whether emergent entities are real.

    The philosophy on the topic that I’ve read accepts the terms of the arguments as presented by Kim in Making Sense of Emergence. Roughly: Physicalism requires supervenience on the entities of physics at a minimum. Emergentism claims that novel irreducible entities emerge while still supervening. To gain reality for the emergents, these entities are claimed to have irreducible, underivable causal powers. Kim tries to show how the assumption of supervenience contradicts that possibility, eg by over-determining causes if one allows unique causal powers for the emergents.

    One counterargument to Kim is via multiple realizability. If higher level entities are can supervene on different physical substrates while retaining a single type, then that would make the causal properties of that type irreducible to the any supervened-upon substrate. But MR has dubious scientific credentials, at least in issues of mental causation. Also, there are arguments that if a type is truly multiply realizable, then it cannot be legitimately considered a single type.

    A more common approach is to look at the nature of the causal properties of the upper level entity and show they stand on their own. One way to doing this is by using a plain counter-factual approach to causation, as with early Davidson. But this approach has serious philosophical issues (eg how to derive the outcomes of the counter factual cases without appeal to eg regularity principles). And Kim claims that it is unintuitive to apply counterfactual causation to mental causation in particular, since it ignores our intuition of agency which seems to involve some kind of process/transfer of energy in causation, not just counterfactual cases.

    Instead, a more scientifically-friendly and sophisticated notion of causality is used to argue against Kim. Woodward’s interventionist approach seems helpful: it combines counter-factualism with the concepts of Bayesian networks, an important tool for determining causality in the special sciences. For example, his Mental Causation and Neural Mechanisms does an nice job of examining Kim’s concerns and how to counter them via interventionist models of causation.

    Now why does this relate to L&R? I know they reject Kim’s metaphysics and concepts like supervenience. Instead, I understand them to be saying the real patterns detected by each special science provide all the needed ontological justification for the entities and their associated causal powers within each separate special science.

    But how do you justify the reality of the patterns in those sciences? I think through the scientific disciplines each applies. And that means you need to use the scientifically accepted notions of causality in those domains. Which brings us back to the considerations raised (eg) by Woodward.

  31. unsurprisingly, keiths is oblivious to the teleological nature of the word mechanism.

    watch him wiggle free of it though, through pedantic feats of semantic wizardry.

  32. Dr. Liddle retorts “NOPE”. Gotta love the speed at which she rips apart a logical observation.

    Thanks though, for catching that transposition. Its a common enough spelling error for that particular arrangement of letters.

    Voila does sound a whole lot better than viola.

    Elizabeth: Can you explain what you mean by this?

    Not really.

    Certainly.

    That’s implicit in OoL

    Nope.

    Nope.

    I think you’ll find that Sherlock played the violin, not the viola.

  33. keiths:
    Reciprocating Bill,

    I haven’t heard about Dennett’s upcoming book. What do you know about it?

    Kantian Naturalist mentioned it upthread. That’s all I know about the book. I know Dennett was very favorably impressed with Millikan’s Language, Thought and Other Biological Categories, which directly deals with the nature of “function” in biology, as far back as The Intentional Stance (I think).

  34. actually in the darwinian evolutionary narrative, reproduction is not implicit in OoL. first comes the most basic proto-cell by sheer culmination of undirected, goalless particles of matter clumped together by happenstance.

    THEN, somehow basic reproduction. THEN, somehow multi-cellularity. THEN, somehow complicated mechanisms to handle the reproduction of multi-cellular organisms. THEN, somehow a digestive system (mindful of the notion that digestion presupposes the need to nutrients), THEN somehow a motility mechanism (mindful that movement presupposes a need to move). THEN somehow a sensory mechanism (mindful that senses pre-suppose a need to navigate).

    The evolution narrative only gets off the ground by assuming early life miraculously avoided shipwrecks over and over again. Not just reproductive shipwrecks, but sensory wrecks, motility wrecks, digestive wrecks, defensive wrecks, all kinds of wrecks. On and on and on.

  35. Kantian Naturalist: However, I think that progress can be made by following a very interesting suggestion by Rebecca Kukla about how to understand Dennettian stances

    I enjoyed that paper and its new approach to Dennett.

    But I am concerned that her arguments lead to “Richard Rorty’s milder-than-mild irrealism, according to which the pattern is only in the eyes of the beholders” (quoted from the concluding section of Real Patterns). Dennett says he wants to and does avoid this irrealism.

    I’m thinking of statements like these from her paper:

    [p 11] it  seems  that  I  am  committed  to  saying  that  being  real  or  objective  is  not an  all-­-or-­-nothing  thing  –  that  an  entity  can  be  roughly  and  approximately  real,  even  though there  is  no  separate  standard  of  the  ‘really  real’  that  it  is  failing  to  meet.  This  is  a  bullet  I  am pleased  to  bite.  

    [p. 21]One  can  ask  questions  about  what  is  real  from  within  any  stance, and  one  can,  upon investigation,  give  fallible  but  well-­-supported  answers. One  will  get  these  answers  by employing  the  body  of  coping  strategies  available  from  that  stance.

    As I understand her argument, it is saying that the objects of the intentional stance gain their reality by the success of each individual’s coping strategies. In particular, I don’t see anything specific in the paper about moving beyond the individual in an objective way. Dennett, on the other hand, talks both about the winning of bets by the objectively correct balancing of simplicity and predictive power, and also about the “statistical effect of very many concrete minutiae producing, as if by a hidden hand, an approximation of the ‘ideal’ order”, which he relates to Churchlandian connectionism and so neuroscience, I believe.

    I believe you raise a similar concern when you differentiate a stance from a pose in your discussion of religion and magic. You say:

    Religious practices are poses because when it does genuinely engage with reality in terms of managing group dynamics and enforcing shared norms of conduct, not in terms of untestable pseudo-explanations.

    I think there is a typo there which means I am having some trouble parsing your point, but I believe you are saying that stances require objective testability, poses do not. I that that appeal to testability requires the objective disciplines of science, and it seems to me that her arguments lack access to those resources.

  36. Elizabeth (in reply to Neil Rickert): Right.And this is absolutely key, I think, and the point I was trying to make (but you make better) in an early OP (can’t remember which one): that science isn’t biased against non-mechanistic models, it’s rather that they are the only kind that science can do.Whether or not you think there are more things in heaven and earth horatio than are dreamt of in your scientific models, or not, is a matter of belief, not of science.

    Unless of course you recognize “Goethean science” as a science. Modern “Science” is very well suited to the study of inorganic nature where things are reduced to their fundamental properties. But I would say if we are looking for the fundamental entity in the organic realm it would be the whole organism. When an organism is reduced to fundamental particles it is no longer a living being but becomes dead matter.

    Gordon L. Miller in the introduction to The Metamorphosis of Plants writes:

    The process of dialectical development envisioned by Goethe helps fashion the mutual “fitness” of organism and environment, but he did not see this process as fulfilling any predesigned purposes or aiming for any fixed ends. Rejecting the classical notion of external teleology in nature, he proposed that we can “attain a more satisfactory insight into the mysterious architecture of the formative process” if we study “how nature expresses itself from all quarters and in all directions as it goes about its work of creation.” For Goethe, the integrity and rising intensity of the inner impulse, the creativity of which sometimes issues in complexities of form far beyond the needs of mere survival, gives natural things a degree of autonomy and a measure of intrinsic value. They, and nature in toto, are destined not for particular—and particularly anthropocentric—ends, but rather are striving for the internal satisfaction of wholeness…

    Because supersensible archetypes or objective ideas in nature are not things recognized by mainstream modern science, many have been led to reject Goethe’s scientific approach as suffering too much from the romantic musings of his poetic genius. But to aim this criticism at Goethe’s way of science is merely to beg the question he was posing about the limits of mainstream science: Can a mechanistic, materialistic approach that focuses only on innumerable individual surface structures meet the explanatory challenge of the living organism or the life of nature as a whole? His sense that the world we experience could never be built up from mere matter in motion, nor truly known on the model of a human subject confronting a mere object, spurred him to develop his alternative approach

    From Craig Holdrege

    Goethe’s approach to science was truly ecological—he always tried to understand things in relation to their broader connections. He was keenly aware of the errors that occur when we focus too exclusively on isolated details—whether in observation of natural phenomena or in carrying out experiments. In his seminal little essay “The Experiment as Mediator of Subject and Object,” written in 1792, Goethe discusses scientific methodology. Because he had learned that “in living nature nothing happens that is not in connection with a whole,” he believed that a scientist must take utmost care when looking at individual facts or performing individual experiments.

    Goethe’s empiricism goes beyond the senses but he adds nothing to the phenomena which does not already belong to the real nature of those phenomena. He did not deny teleology in nature. He just thought that there were better avenues of enquiry than to ask, “what purpose is served by some form or other”.

  37. BruceS,

    That’s interesting objection to Kukla’s argument. In response, I would want to stress the social as well as embodied character of stances, in part because of how one learns to take up a stance, and in part because the testability of subjunctive conditionals requires shared criteria for testability.

    I also suspect — though this is more tentative on my part — that one way we can retrospectively distinguish between stances and poses is based on whether different participants in the stance exhibit any convergence in their judgments over time. Convergence in judgment over time (under “ideal” communicative conditions — communication not distorted by power dynamics, all have equal access to relevant evidence, etc.) is, by pragmatist lights (ever since Peirce!) a reliable indicator of objective reality, even if the objective realities in question are only disclosed from the perspective of a particular stance.

    Reciprocating Bill: Kantian Naturalist mentioned it upthread. That’s all I know about the book. I know Dennett was very favorably impressed with Millikan’s Language, Thought and Other Biological Categories, which directly deals with the nature of “function” in biology, as far back as The Intentional Stance (I think).

    I only heard about it from a friend of mine the other day. All I was told is that it returns to questions about teleology and function. In some recent work he’s been arguing that we can’t explain biological phenomena without talking about reasons.

  38. Kantian Naturalist:

    n part because of how one learns to take up a stance, and in part because the testability of subjunctive conditionals requires shared criteria for testability.

    But if we need objective, “shared” criteria to claim reality for whatever the stances “grapple with”, why wouldn’t that show that whatever they are grappling with must have been already there? Then we could use that justification of pre-existence as the basis of the target’s reality, not its detection by stances.

    Which is what I take Dennett to be at least gesturing at in his spin of Churchland in Real Patterns when he tries to explain his version of realism.

  39. BruceS: But I am concerned that her arguments lead to “Richard Rorty’s milder-than-mild irrealism, according to which the pattern is only in the eyes of the beholders” (quoted from the concluding section of Real Patterns). Dennett says he wants to and does avoid this irrealism.

    Why is this “irrealism”.

    I see nothing more realistic, than that patterns are of our creation. What I see as unreal, is the widely held view that there are human independent patterns and that cognition works by finding them. I see this mistake as a major failure of philosophy.

  40. Neil,

    What I see as unreal, is the widely held view that there are human independent patterns and that cognition works by finding them.

    So you would say that the pattern of, say, a salt crystal is not human-independent?

  41. Lizzie,

    But practice is all we’ve got, keiths.

    It’s all we’ve got, but the demon doesn’t share our limitations.

    If it wants to model a fellow demon then it’s stuck.

    In which case a meta-demon is required. 🙂

    Remember, we are responding to William’s claim that intention is ontologically real and independent of mechanism. According to William, the fact that we need to invoke teleology in our models is evidence for the reality of that mechanism-independent version of intention.

    If we can predict outcomes without recourse to anything other than mechanism — even if this is possible only in principle, not in practice — then we have falsified William’s claim. We have shown that intention arises from mechanism and is not independent of it.

  42. keiths: So you would say that the pattern of, say, a salt crystal is not human-independent?

    Separating out something and calling it a salt crystal is already human dependent.

  43. Neil Rickert:

    I see nothing more realistic than that patterns are of our creation.What I see as unreal, is the widely held view that there are human independent patterns and that cognition works by finding them.I see this mistake as a major failure of philosophy.

    HI Neil:

    I think we’ve been through our positions about scientific realism in past threads.

    In this thread, I understand that “domains of separate sciences” is sometimes replaced by and possibly expanded by “stances”. I think and I understand KN thinks that to consider the entities of each to be real requires objectively-justified explanations, where the norms/guidelines for assessing explanations as objective are themselves pragmatically justified as I’ve outlined previously in the thread.

    So it comes down to whether the success of sciences in predicting novelty and in manipulation justifies a philosophical conclusion that the entities and/or structures captured by the models of the theories can be considered objectively real.

    I say they can. I understand from past discussions that you don’t see it that way. Fair enough.

    (My concern with Kukla is that she seems to have omitted the objectivity that Dennett was concerned with. Of course, she may not think that is an important omission).

Leave a Reply